From the section: 5 Emotions' Mysterious Objects (1984)From the section entitled: D. The Existence of Objects: Actual and Possible
Robert C. Solomon wrote:The object of an emotion is a situation, thing, person, etc., as viewed in a certain way. In a complete account, it will be necessary to specify, for each emotion as well as for emotions in general, what this "certain way" is. In pride, for example, the "certain way" is, as Hume rightly argued, seeing the object as signifying one's own virtue.
Hume rightly argued, seeing the object as signifying one's own virtue --- this is plainly not the whole picture though - lets face it - the mood comes into play - the complex pattern that the overall emotional state forms which feeds back through other systems is likely if you were to take my model into consideration.
Robert C. Solomon wrote:Furthermore, Wilson's position becomes patently absurd for emotions directed toward the future (or past). It becomes logically impossible to hope for anything; indeed, in one sense, it would be impossible even to be afraid (since the event feared, as distinct from the being that will cause that event, is in the future). The objects of emotion clearly need not be "items existing in the world." Nevertheless, it is nonsense to suppose that, in most cases, the objects of emotion are anything else.
The object of emotion can be imaginary - the thought can be directed at the future. People do experience emotions with non physical objects and in turn experience physiological responses. In the case of a mortgage a person can spend a lot of time in their life experiencing stress that is physiologically affective.
Robert C. Solomon wrote:The objects of emotion may be the objects of imagination, memory, and contemplation as well as those of perception.
And I was saying . . . The psychological impending doom that one imposes upon oneself as in the case of the mortgage for example happens when the person in question keeps thinking about a foreclosure. Not limited to the case of the mortgage either - in effect our fight and flight response were made for us to flee or fight in short bursts rather than the long drawn out emotional turmoil that can also raise the adrenaline but over longer periods leading to a rise in cortisol which can affect the immune system - being the effect caused by the stress of an imagined impending doom. In this case a lot of other factors clearly come into play if the person has no reason to be imagining the impending doom in the first place.
From the section entitled: F. Emotions, Descriptions, and Objects: Beyond Atomism
Robert C. Solomon wrote:In our preceding discussions, we have left unchallenged one major assumption, shared by virtually every author on the subject—namely, the assumption that an emotion and its object are distinct entities, however each of them is to be analyzed. Thus Hume sharply distinguished the impression that is the emotion from the ideas which are its cause and object. Kenny sharply distinguishes the emotion, which is a "feeling," from the object, the thing, event, or state of affairs to which this feeling has a "special non-causal" relationship. Wilson, flatly rejecting Kenny's analysis in general, still begins his analysis with the same flat-footed distinction: "If I am afraid of a dog, the dog and my fear are distinct items in any sense of the word."
I do question this somewhat - is it actually necessary to be so focused on the emotion and its object - I do not deny that both are important to consider just that once the event or object has already taken place in the world it becomes a task for the mind/body(brain) to take care of. This seems to me to be an over production of reality. Even though we are bound to reality - once we have sensed it the object becomes the domain of the mind.
Robert C. Solomon wrote:The traditional conceptions of emotions have been attacked often and convincingly, but what has rarely been offered is an alternative. I would argue that emotions can be understood as systems of judgments, which constitute a particular kind of world view.
I would argue the same thing here - just that I would probably use a different word than judgment - I might however warm up to the word. Just the same it is quite apparent that we are dealing with some sort of whole system made up of subsystems by virtue of the fact that we - humans - structure our information on these topics as such - there is more than one way of doing the same thing.
From the Conclusion:
Robert C. Solomon wrote:The concept of "intentionality" captures an essential but misleading property of emotions. It points to the fact that emotions are not merely "feelings" but ways of seeing, ways of directing one's experience of the world. But the concept of intentionality also suggests some too extravagant ontological projections, and it suggests, too, that an emotion and its object are two distinct phenomena, with a problematic if not downright "mysterious" connection between them.
For me the object once it has become the domain of the mind is an "impression", only it is a complex impression, as in a pattern. The emotion related to this pattern is a process that was already in a positive or negative state of progress - akin to weighting - much like an action potential but on a grander scale. The process increments a state of analysis on the pattern - once the process has performed many states of analysis and updated the emotional system the perception comes into light - so to speak.
The main difference I notice between imagined "objects" and real "objects" is the mind does work with both separately and in a different way - there is a time factor involved and usually the person doing the imagining is experiencing the lag that the event/object has not taken place yet in reality - this correlates well with lower levels of adrenaline over longer periods for an imagined impending doom. Another thought is that when something happens in reality that there are in fact two objects to the emotion - the real object and the object as it is assimilated by the mind.